title
macrohistory.com

(HEALTH, GEOLOGY, BIOLOGY and SOCIOLOGY – continued)

home | 18-19th centuries index

HEALTH, GEOLOGY, BIOLOGY and SOCIOLOGY (3 of 3)

previous | next

The Sociologists Auguste Comte and Herbert Spencer

Earlier in the century, a Frenchman, Auguste Comte (1798-1857), advocated a philosophy that tied together everything that was knowable through the senses. Comte believed that history had passed through stages of religiosity and was coming into what he called the positivist stage, an age of science.

Comte lumped together history and politics, biology and anything else that could be studied empirically into what he called sociology. His sociology by observation included experimentation such as altering a segment of society to study its effects, and it consisted of comparative research, such as animal societies compared to human society and comparing different human societies around the globe. By using sociology, he believed, a new and stable society could be created on scientific principles.

It was an illusion. Science was about measuring, categorizing and seeing connections. And together these did not tell people what should be done about it. Comte's sociology produced no blueprint for action that would be accepted widely enough to be politically effective. It was an attempt at complete knowledge that would provide politicians with an excuse not to act, to ask instead for a study. Knowledge is useful, and sociologists would be helpful. The field of sociology would produce people with admirable minds and a good breadth of knowledge, but if one waited for complete knowledge nothing would get done.

A social reality not adequately considered by Comte was conflicting values. These values might be measured statistically, but the values themselves would not be up for manipulation, nor value conflicts readily resolved. Marxists in power and believing in scientific socialism would try without success. The scientific socialists would themselves disagree about what was to be done and make a bloody mess of their conflict with each other. Science was one thing; values another.

Philosophical differences were not slow in developing among the sociologists. Those who followed Comte were less optimistic about their discipline producing the perfect society. Among them was a British philosopher Herbert Spencer (1820-1903), an avowed "agnostic." He had been an evolutionist before Darwin's publication of Origins of the Species but without an effective theory of natural selection. Spencer wrote of organisms developing from simple to more complex forms and spoke of this as progress. Spencer, not Darwin, coined the phrase "survival of the fittest," and Darwin, in later editions of his Origins of the Species employed Spencer's phrase.

Spencer believed that human behavior was primarily organized toward self-preservation. He recognized that people were social, that people acted together for mutual self-defense and that they remained tied together by a natural sympathy and concern for each other. Humans, he believed, had an innate sense of morality and had a compassion for their fellow humans that extended beyond the family unit. Spencer believed that men were political creatures. Like Aristotle he believed that societies functioned best when they allowed a degree of liberty to individuals. The only liberty that should be restricted, he held, was that which was necessary to preserve liberty in general.

Spencer's "survival of the fittest" fit well with the free-wheeling capitalism of his day. He believed in competition unfettered by government interference. Let the most able rise, he believed. And some exceptional people did rise, and some fools fell. But human societies were not as biologically determined as some lower forms of life. In human societies people as a group could make choices. That is what they did when they made laws. Spencer was simplistic in focusing on competition and individualism to the exclusion of cooperation. His view lacked balance.

Spencer spoke in opposition to any interference in economic matters by the state. He was anti-regulation. He was opposed to factory inspections. He opposed various labor laws or the state providing any kind of welfare. And the state, he believed, should not be involved in education. These views he saw as a product of his science, and he heaped scorn upon study that involved choice that included emotions and value judgments: the liberal arts.

Copyright © 2009-2014 by Frank E. Smitha. All rights reserved.